Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics
Section Language
and Politics – Ed. Ruth Wodak
Politics,
Ideology and
Discourse
Teun
A. van Dijk
Universitat Pompeu
Fabra,
Second version,
Introduction
Few areas in the social sciences are as closely related as those of the study of politics, ideology and discourse. Politics is one of the social domains whose practices are virtually exclusively discursive; political cognition is by definition ideologically based; and political ideologies are largely reproduced by discourse. In this chapter we examine these relationships more closely.
Ideology
The concept of ‘ideology’ is often used in the media and the social sciences, but it is notoriously vague. Its everyday usage is largely negative, and typically refers to the rigid, misguided or partisan ideas of others: we have the truth, and they have ideologies. This negative meaning goes back to Marx-Engels, for whom ideologies were a form of ‘false consciousness’; thus, the working class may have misguided ideas about the conditions of its existence as a result of their indoctrination by those who control the means of production. Throughout large part of the 20th century, and both in politics and in the social sciences, the notion of ideology continued to carry its negative connotation, and was often used in opposition to ‘objective’ knowledge (for histories of the notion of ideology, see, e.g., Billig, 1982; Eagleton, 1991; Larrain, 1979; for a useful collection of classical studies on ideology, see Zizek, 1994).
Originally, ‘ideology’ did not have this negative meaning. More than two hundred years ago, the French philosopher Destutt de Tracy introduced the term in order to denote a new discipline that would study ‘ideas’: idéologie. Also in contemporary political science, the notion is used in a more neutral, descriptive sense, e.g., to refer to political belief systems (Freeden, 1996).
One of the many dimensions highlighted in the classical approaches to ideology was their ‘dominant’ nature, in the sense that ideologies play a role in the legitimization of power abuse by dominant groups. One of the most efficient forms of ideological dominance is when also the dominated groups accept dominant ideologies as ‘natural’ or ‘commonsense’. Gramsci called such forms of ideological dominance ‘hegemony’ (Gramsci, 1971). Bourdieu does not use the notion of ideology very much (mainly because he thinks it is too vague and has often been abused to discredit others who do not agree with us; see Bourdieu & Eagleton, 1994), but rather speaks of symbolic power or symbolic violence. It should be stressed though that although related his uses of these terms are different from the (various) uses of the notion of ideology. His main interest lies in the social conditions of discursive and symbolic power, such as the authority and legitimacy of those who produce discourse.
To cut a long historical survey short, a specific concept of ideology will be used in this chapter, namely to describe specific, fundamental beliefs of groups of people. Our working definition of ideologies is therefore as follows: An ideology is the foundation of the social representations shared by a social group. Depending on one’s perspective, group membership or ethics, these group ideas may be valued ‘positively’, ‘negatively’ or not be valued at all. That is, we do not exclusively identify ideologies with dominant groups (see also the discussion in Abercrombie, Hill & Turner, 1980). Also dominated groups may have ideologies, namely ideologies of resistance and opposition. Ideologies more generally are associated with social groups, classes, casts or communities which thus represent their fundamental interests. The theory accounting for such ideological beliefs is complex and multidisciplinary, and may be summarized as follows (for details and many further references, see Van Dijk, 1998):
· Ideologies have both social and cognitive properties which need to be accounted for in an integrated theory.
· Cognitively, ideologies are a special kind of social belief systems, stored in Long Term Memory. (See Mental Representation).
· Socially as well as cognitively, these ideological belief systems are socially shared by the members of specific social groups or ‘ideological communities’. (See Distributed cognition and communication).
· Ideologies, like languages, are essentially social. There are no ‘personal’ or ‘individual’ ideologies – only personal or individual ‘uses’ of ideologies.
· The identity of groups is not only based on their ‘structural’ properties, but also on their ideology.
· Ideological belief systems – ideologies -- form the ‘axiomatic’ basis of the more specific beliefs or ‘social representations’ of a group, such as their group knowledge and group opinions (attitudes).
· Unlike in most traditional approaches to ideology, ideologies are not necessarily ‘negative.’ They have similar structures and functions whether shared by dominant or dominated groups, ‘bad’ groups or ‘good’ groups. Thus, we may have negative as well as positive ideologies (‘utopias’), depending on the perspective, values or group membership of the one who evaluates them.
· Not all socially shared beliefs of a group are ideological. Thus, ideologically different or opposed groups in the same society need to have beliefs in common in order to be able to communicate in the first place. This Common Ground consists of socioculturally shared knowledge, which by definition is pre-ideological within that society (although it may later or elsewhere be described as ideological knowledge).
· Thus, the traditionally problematic relationship between knowledge and ideology is resolved as follows: General, sociocultural knowledge, shared by an epistemic community, forms the common ground for all social representations of all (ideological) groups in that community. However, each group may develop specific group knowledge (e.g., professional, religious or political knowledge) based on the ideology of the group. This knowledge is called ‘knowledge’ within the group because it is generally shared, certified and presupposed to be ‘true’. For other groups such knowledge may of course be called ‘mere belief’, superstition or religion. In other words, beliefs that are taken for granted, commonsense, non-disputed, etc. within a community, and shared by different ideological groups, is by definition non-ideological within that community.
· Ideologies embody the general principles that control the overall coherence of the social representations shared by the members of a group. For instance, a racist ideology may control more specific attitudes about immigration or affirmative action.
· Ideologically based social representations (such as feminist attitudes about abortion or glass ceilings on the job), are general and abstract. In order to relate to concrete social practices and discourses about specific events, they need to become contextualized and specified in mental models. These (ideological biased) mental models, stored in Episodic Memory, are the mental constructs that control discourse, interaction and other social practices. And conversely, it is through mental models that discourses are able to influence social representations and ideologies and reproduce these. (See Cognition, Emotion and Language).
· Ideologies represent one of the dimensions of the social identity or self-image of groups.
· Unlike less fundamental social representations and much more than variable personal models, ideologies are relatively stable. One does not become or cease to be a feminist, socialist or pacifist overnight. Many ideologies are acquired over many years and remain active for a lifetime of group members.
· Ideologies are structured by a social schema consisting of a number of categories that cognitively represent the major social dimensions of groups, such as their distinguishing properties, membership criteria, typical actions, goals, norms and values, reference groups and basic resources or interests.
· Both cognitively as well as socially, ideologies develop especially as socially shared resources for intragroup cohesion and cooperation, as well as for efficient means for intergroup relations.
· Many – but not all -- ideologies are relevant in situations of competition, conflict, domination and resistance between groups, that is, as part of a social struggle. This also explains why many of the mental structures of ideologies and ideological practices are polarized on the basis of an ingroup-outgroup differentiation, typically between Us and Them¸ as also ideological discourses show.
· Because individual people may be members of several groups, they may ‘participate’ in various ideologies. Thus, someone may be a nationalist, socialist, feminist journalist, and thus share in the ideologies of these different kinds of social and professional ideologies. Obviously, when activated (used) at the same time, in discourse or other social practices, this may sometimes lead to conflicts.
· The social practices, and hence discourses, of group members may be (indirectly) controlled by group ideologies, but are usually mediated by more specific social representations at the group level and by concrete, personal mental models at the individual level.
· Conversely, ideologies are personally acquired and socially reproduced by the social practices, and especially the discourses, of a group.
· Groups may organize the discursive acquisition and reproduction of ideologies, for instance through special forms of education, indoctrination, job training, or catechesis, and by specialized group members (ideologues, priests, teachers, etc.) and in special institutions.
· Not all group members have – nor need to have – the same level of ideological knowledge or expertise, nor need their ideological knowledge always be very explicit. Using an ideology is like being able to use a language without being able to formulate the grammar of that language. Many men are sexist and their sexist ideology may control much of their discourse and other social practices, but they need not always have explicit access to the contents of their ideologies.
· However, since many social ideologies develop as part of group relations, conflict or domination and resistance, and hence involve ideological debate that is often published in the mass media, many group members know at least the main ideological tenets of their group – and of other groups. Indeed, when their interests are threatened they often know how and why to protect these.
These are some of the main properties of ideologies as formulated in a multidisciplinary, socio-cognitive theory. Thus, ideologies are the ‘axiomatic’ basis of the social representations of a group and – through specific social attitudes and then through personal mental models -- control the individual discourses and other social practices of group members. In this way they also are the necessary resource of ingroup cooperation, coordination and cohesion, as well as for the management of intergroup relations, competition, conflict or struggle. It is only within such a theory that we are able to account for ideological discourse and other social practices, namely as being derived from ideologically based social representations, and as instantiations of social relations between groups.
More than traditional approaches, this multidisciplinary approach not only emphasizes the social and political nature of ideologies, but also their sociocognitive nature. It should be emphasized though that this does not mean that especially or only this cognitive dimension is important. Unlike traditional social or socioeconomic approaches, the theory emphasizes that –trivially-- ideologies have to do with ideas of some kind, and hence also need a cognitive account besides a social theory of groups and group relations, power and interests. The point is that these different approaches need and can be integrated in one multidisciplinary theory. Hence, this approach does imply that a theory of ideology without an explicit cognitive component is incomplete: dealing about ideologies without talking about the nature and functions of socially shared ‘ideas’ is theoretically unsatisfactory.
We see that ideological social practices are by definition based on ideologies defined as shared mental representations of some kind, in a way that might be compared with the way language use is ‘based’ on a shared grammar or discourse and conversation rules. It is in this sense that ideologies as socially shared cognitive resources are fundamental for social practices, interaction and intra- and intergroup relations. Conversely, the general social functions of ideological practices must hence be represented as part of their ‘underlying’ ideologies. This is one of the many reasons why cognitive and social approaches to ideology need to be integrated.
The theory proposed here accounts for both the relatively stable as well as the flexible, dynamic, changing, contextualized and subjective aspects of ideology. The first dimension is explained in terms of relatively stable, socially shared mental representations of groups. The second dimension is accounted for by ideologically based, specific, subjective mental models of group members that control discourse and other social practices in each situation. Unlike other approaches, for instance in discursive psychology and other constructionist approaches (Billig, 1988, 1991; Potter, 1996), this theory does not attribute the flexible, subjective or contextually variable aspects of ideological practices to the nature of ideology itself, but to its ‘uses’ by individual members. Again, the comparison with relatively stable – and slowly changing – grammars of natural languages, and their variable, contextualized, personal uses, suggests itself. For the same reason, ideologies are not reduced to their ‘observable’ uses, discourses or other social practices, but defined as members’ socially shared underlying representations or resources that govern such practices. Nor do we reduce ideologies to discourses, because obviously they control also other social practices, such as forms of discrimination or violence. In sum, the theory presented here is not only multidisciplinary, but also non-reductionist.
Finally, ideologies are accounted for in sociocognitive rather than in emotional terms, because they are by definition socially shared, and in our definition of emotions, only individual persons and not groups can have, bodily based, emotions. When we sometimes speak of ideologies of ‘hate’, as is the case for racist or sexist ideologies, we are not speaking of emotions but of shared negative evaluations (opinions). Emotions are temporal, contextual and personal, physiologically based, and cognitively interpreted events. Thus one can have and share a more or less permanent negative opinion about immigrants, but one cannot, in the strict sense of the term be permanently ‘angry’ about immigrants, nor literally share an emotion with others. Thus, since ideologies are socially shared, they by definition cannot be ‘emotional’. However, their uses or applications by individual group members in concrete situations may of course trigger and be expressed as emotions. Also for this reasons it is essential to analytically distinguish between ideologies and their actual uses or manifestations in discourse, interaction and other social practices.
Ideology
and politics
The general theory of ideology summarized above needs to be specified for the huge social ‘field’ of politics, that is, for politicians, political cognition, political processes, political practices and political discourse as characterizing political groups, such as political parties, members of parliaments or social movements. As soon as ideologies not only have general social functions but more specifically (also) political functions in the field of politics, we shall call them political ideologies. Thus, socialism is more obviously a ‘political’ ideology than the professional ideology of dentists, as long as we interpret ‘political’ here as describing processes in the field of politics – and not as part of the fields of health care, education or justice, among others. Thus, one way of classifying ideologies – as well as discourses -- is by the social field in which they function. That is, we have political, educational, legal, religious and health care ideologies, among others.
It is beyond the scope of this brief chapter to define and theorize in detail about what characterizes the field of politics (see, e.g., Goodin & Klingemann, 1996). However, apart from being defined by its prototypical participants (politicians), this field may briefly – and somewhat traditionally – be defined by
· its overall systems (democracy, dictatorship, etc.),
· special social macro actions, such as government, legislation, elections, or decision making,
· and their micro practices, interactions or discourses such as parliamentary debates, canvassing or demonstrations,
· its special social relations, such as those of institutional power,
· its special norms and values (e.g., freedom, equality, etc.)
· its political cognitions, such as political ideologies.
If there is one social field that is ideological, it is that of politics. This is not surprising because it is eminently here that different and opposed groups, power, struggle and interests are at stake. In order to be able to compete, political groups need to be ideologically conscious and organized. Few ideological groups besides political parties have ‘programs’ that formulate their ideologies explicitly, and that compete for new members or supporters on that basis. Few ideologies are as explicitly defended and contested as political ideologies, as we know from the history of socialism, communism, liberalism, and so on. In other words, the political process is essentially an ideological process, and political cognition often simply identified with ideology (see Freeden, 1996; Ball & Dagger, 1999; Eatwell, 1999; Leach, 2002; Seliger, 1976)
The social organization of the field of politics, and hence of politicians and political groups, is largely based on ideological differences, alliances and similarities. The overall organization of social beliefs as a struggle between the Left and the Right is the result of the underlying polarization of political ideologies that has permeated society as a whole. Elections, parliaments, political campaigns, propaganda, demonstrations, and many other phenomena of the political field are thus profoundly ideological. Debates in parliament pitch opposed political ideologies as basis for political policies, measures, decisions or actions. One’s political identity, stances and allegiances are not so much defined in structural group membership, such as membership of a political party, but rather in terms of one’s ideology. Most socialists or neoliberals do not have a membership card. The same is true for other social ideologies that have profound political implications, such as feminism, pacifism, ecologism or racism.
Although primarily defined in sociocognitive terms, political ideologies permeate the whole political field, such as overall systems such as democracies (based on democratic ideologies), overall acts and processes (such as government, coalition building, or elections), everyday political practices (such as parliamentary debates or demonstrations), group relations (such as domination and resistance, government or opposition), fundamental norms and values (such as equality and independence that are constitutive categories of ideologies), as well as more specific political attitudes (for instance about legislation about abortion or divorce) that are controlled by ideologies.
Political discourse and ideology
If the political field is thoroughly ideological, then so are its political practices, and hence its discourses (among the many books on political discourse, see, e.g., Chilton, 1995, 2004; Chilton & Schäffner, 2002; Wilson, 1990; Wodak & Menz, 1990; see also the other contributions to this section). Indeed, political ideologies not only are involved in the production or understanding of political discourses and other political practices, but are also (re)produced by them. In a sense discourses make ideologies ‘observable’ in the sense that it is only in discourse that they may be explicitly ‘expressed’ and ‘formulated’. Other political practices only implicitly show or experience ideologies, for instance in practices of discrimination on the basis of sexist, racist or political ideologies. It is in discourse that we need to explicitly explain that such discrimination occurs ‘because she is a woman’, ‘because he is black’ or ‘because they are socialists’.
Thus, it is largely through discourse that political
ideologies are acquired, expressed, learned, propagated and contested.
The rest
of this chapter will be about these relationships between political
discourse
and political ideologies. Interestingly, despite the vast literature on
ideology (thousands of books in English alone), there are virtually no
monographs that explore the details of the relations between discourse
and
ideology, although many books in critical linguistics and critical
discourse
analysis deal with at least some aspects of this relationship (see,
e.g., Fairclough, 1989, 1995; Fowler,
Hodge, Kress & Trew, 1979; Fowler,
1991; Hodge & Kress, 1993; Pêcheux,
1982; Van Dijk, 1998; Wodak, 1989; Wodak et al.,
1987; Wodak & Menz, 1990; Wodak &
Meyer, 2001).
Political situations and contexts
The relations between discourse and political ideologies are usually studied in terms of the structures of political discourse, such as the use of ‘biased’ lexical items, syntactic structures such as actives and passives, pronouns such as us and them, metaphors or topoi, arguments, implications and many others properties of discourse (see the references given at the end of the last section).
It should be emphasized though that discourse should be
conceptualized also in terms of its context
structures (Duranti & Goodwin, 1992).
It is not
sufficient to observe, for instance, that political discourse often
features
the well-known ‘political’ pronoun we.
It is crucial to relate such use to such categories as who
is speaking, when, where and with/to whom, that is, to specific
aspects of the political situation.
Since such political situations do not simply ‘cause’ political actors to speak in such a way, we again need a cognitive interface between such a situation and talk or text, that is, a mental model of the political situation (van Dijk, 1999, 2001, 2003). Such mental models define how participants experience, interpret and represent the for-them-relevant aspects of the political situation. These specific mental models are called contexts. In other words, contexts are subjective participant definitions of communicative situations. They control all aspects of discourse production and comprehension.
Political discourse, thus, is not only defined in terms of political discourse structures but also in terms of political contexts. Thus, acting an MP, prime minister, party leader, or demonstrator will typically be perceived by speakers or recipients as a political relevant context category in political discourse, whereas being a dentist or a doorkeeper much less so. Similarly, political contexts may be defined by special settings, featuring locations such as parliamentary buildings or events such as debates or meetings, as often controlled by precise timing, as is the case in parliamentary debates. And political discourses and their structures will only be able to have the political functions they have when they are enacting political acts or processes, such as governing, legislation or ‘doing’ opposition, and with very specific political aims in mind, such as defending or defeating a bill or getting elected. And finally, political actors obviously do not participate mindlessly in political situations, but have political knowledge, share political norms and values, as well as political ideologies. Indeed, it is through this form of contextualization that we are able to link the ideologies of the participants to their discourses (Gumperz, 1982). Text or talk ‘show’ ideologies discursively, but it is people, politicians or protesters, who ‘have’ ideologies – not only in this social practice or discourse, but typically also in others.
These then are some of the kind of categories that make up our political context models – that is, political categories that we use to define political situations of text and talk. In the same way as discourses may be ideological when based on ideologies, also the structures and practices of political contexts may have such an ideological basis. Obviously, being an MP presupposes a parliamentary system and hence a democratic ideology, whereas being a dictator presupposes another ideology.
Obviously these categories are culturally variable: members of parliament, prime ministers or party secretaries are not exactly universal political participant categories. Other cultures may have their own specific political event types, political actions, participants, locations, time management, and of course their own political knowledge, attitudes, ideologies, norms and values.
A detailed explanation of the cognitive processes
involved in the way context models control political discourse is
beyond the
scope of this chapter. Suffice it to say that the information in the
various
categories of the (pragmatic) context model – for instance who are
participating in the communicative situation – first of all controls
the speech
acts and other acts of the current situation. Thus, the current
utterance may
be defined as a political promise or as a threat, depending on the
power or
relationships of the participants, their political position (government
or
opposition, my party or your party), as well as the intentions to help
or harm
the recipient. Secondly, pragmatic context models control the selection
of
information in the (semantic) mental model that (inter)subjectively
defines
what participants talk about, such as
the war in
Relevant for our discussion in this case is that it is especially the political ideology of the participants that not only controls much of what they say themselves, but also how they will understand other speakers. Thus, a call to limit immigration by an extremist right wing party member will typically be heard and commented upon as ‘racist’, whereas similar proposals by left wing MPs of our own party will obviously seldom be interpreted as such.
Political
discourse and political ideology
If political ideologies are relevant properties of political situations, namely as being shared by participants, then how are they expressed and reproduced by the structures of text and talk?
A first question we need to deal with is whether all properties of political discourse are influenced by ‘underlying’ ideologies? The response to that question is: obviously not, because only those properties of discourse can be influenced by ideologies that can be contextually variable in the first place. Thus, choice of more or less polite pronouns is contextually variable, whereas much of syntactic structure, such as the position of articles in front of nouns in English is not. People of different ideologies do not have different grammars, although they use such grammars sometimes a bit differently. Sociocultural knowledge, including language, defines communities and not ideological groups. In that respect, the left or the right, socialists or neoliberals, racists or antiracists, will not speak or write very differently. This suggests that ideological differences should rather be sought in what people say, rather than in how they say it. Political ideas may be persuasively defended by the Right or the Left, so ideologically differences will hardly be defined only in terms of rhetoric. Thus, although there are probably political uses of discourse forms such as the use of pronouns as ingroup and outgroup markers, or rhetorical means of persuasion, it is likely that most ideological variation will be found at the levels of meaning.
In order to avoid a rather arbitrary discovery procedure of the potentially huge amount of ideologically variable structures of text and talk, it is more useful to proceed in a more systematic and theory-driven way. Thus, we have seen that ideologies often have a polarized structure, reflecting competing or conflicting group membership and categorization in ingroups and outgroups. These underlying structures also appear in more specific political attitudes – for instance racist attitudes about immigration – and ultimately in the biased personal mental models of group members. These mental models control the ‘contents’ of discourse, and if they are polarized, it is likely that discourse will thus also show various types of polarization. Thus, much research has shown that ideological discourse often features the following overall strategies of what might be called the ‘ideological square’:
· Emphasize Our good things
· Emphasize Their bad things
· De-emphasize Our bad things
· De-emphasize Their good things.
These overall strategies may be applied to all levels of action, meaning and form of text and talk. Thus, political speeches, interviews, programs or propaganda typically focus on the preferred topics of ‘our’ group or party, on what we have done well, and associates political opponents with negative topics, such as war, violence, drugs, lack of freedom, and so on. Thus, many politicians and media associate immigrants or minorities with problems or delinquency. For decades communism was associated with aggression, lack of freedom and rigid ideology. Similarly, if communism is good or better than ‘us’ in the area of social services, health care or education, anticommunist discourse will typically ignore or downplay such ‘good things’ of its opponent.
What is true for meanings or topics also hold for form or structure: we may enhance meanings in many ways by intonation or stress, visual or graphical means, word order, headlining, topicalization, repetition, and so on. The opposite will occur when we want to downplay our bad things. Very bad things of our arch enemies – like a terrorist attack-- will thus appear on the front page, in a big article with big negative headlines, or in an emergency debate in parliament, and so on.
In other words, there are systematic means to examine discourse at various levels when looking for ways ideologies are (not) expressed or enacted in such discourse: Whenever a meaning is associated with good things it will tend to be associated with the ingroup of the speaker, and all structural properties of the discourse may be brought to bear to emphasize such meanings. And the opposite will be the case for Others, Opponents or Enemies.
Besides the general, combined strategy of positive
self-presentation and negative other-presentation, ideological
discourse
structures may appear as expressions of other
underlying ideology structures, and not only as an expression of
the
polarized relationship between (opposed) ideological groups. Thus, if
identity,
characteristic actions, aims, norms, values, group relations and
resources are
fundamental ideological categories, we may expect that references to
the
‘contents’ of such categories will be prominent in the discourses of
ideological group members. Thus, if people talk as group
members, in terms of ‘we’, and positively evaluate their
own actions, norms and values, and defend the resources or other
interests of
their group, then such talk will also usually be ideological. Again,
such will
typically be true for the meaning or context of discourse, but the ways
such
meanings are expressed and especially persuasively conveyed may of
course also
involve many formal aspects of grammar, discourse and conversation.
These are the general strategies of ideological discourse production and also a handy discovery or recognition procedure for ideological analysis of political discourse. The more detailed and subtle ideological discourse structures will be examined in a concrete example.
Examples
By way of examples I shall use some fragments from a
debate in the British House of Commons on asylum seekers, held on
In order to enhance the usefulness of our analysis, we shall assign an analytical category to each example, and order the categories alphabetically. After the category name I shall add the domain of discourse analysis to which the category belongs (e.g., meaning, argumentation, etc.). The main point of the analysis is to show how various ideologies, especially those of racism and antiracism, are expressed in various kinds of structures. There are in principle hundreds of such categories, so we make a small selection (for details, see a more detailed ideological analysis in Van Dijk, 2000; no further references are given to the many hundreds of studies that deal with the respective analytical categories mentioned above; see Van Dijk, 1997, for general introduction to many of these notions).
SOME CATEGORIES
OF IDEOLOGICAL DISCOURSE ANALYSIS.
ACTOR
DESCRIPTION
(MEANING).
The way actors are described in discourses also depends on our
ideologies. Typically we tend to describe ingroup members in a neutral
or
positive way, and outgroup members in a negative way. Similarly, we
will
mitigate negative descriptions of members of our own group, and
emphasize the
attributed negative characteristics of Others.
Here is
how Mrs. Gorman describes a Romanian asylum seeker:
(1) In one case, a man from
Romania, who came over here on a coach tour for a football match (…)
decided
that he did not want to go back, declared himself an asylum seeker and
is still
here four years later. He has never done a stroke of work in his life
(Gorman).
AUTHORITY
(ARGUMENTATION). Many speakers in an argument, also in parliament,
have recourse to the fallacy of mentioning authorities to support their
case,
usually organizations or people who are above the fray of party
politics, or
who are generally recognized experts or moral leaders. International
organizations
(such as the United Nations, or Amnesty), scholars, the media, the
church or
the courts often have that role. People of different ideologies
typically cite
different authorities. Thus, Mr. Corbyn ironically asks Mrs. Gorman
whether she
has not read the reports of Amnesty or Helsinki Watch.
BURDEN (TOPOS).
Argumentation against immigration is often based on various standard
arguments,
or topoi, which represent premises that are taken for granted, as
self-evident
and as sufficient reasons to accept the conclusion. One of the topoi of
anti-immigration discourse is that asylum seekers are a financial
‘burden’ for
‘us’:
(2) It is wrong that
ratepayers in the
CATEGORIZATION
(MEANING). As
we also know from social psychology, people tend to categorize
people, and so do speakers in parliament, especially when Others
(immigrants, refugees, etc.) are involved.
Most typical in this debate is the (sub)categorization
of asylum seekers into "genuine" political refugees, and
"bogus" asylum seekers, a categorization formulated in the following
ways:
(3) There are, of course,
asylum seekers and asylum seekers (Gorman).
(4) ... those people, many of
whom could reasonably be called economic migrants and some of whom are
just
benefit seekers on holiday, to remain in
COMPARISON
(MEANING, ARGUMENTATION). Different from rhetorical similes, comparisons as
intended here typically occur in talk about refugees or minorities,
namely when
speakers compare ingroups and outgroups. In racist talk, outgroups are
compared
negatively, and ingroups positively. In antiracist talk we may
negatively
compare our country or government with loathsome undemocratic regimes.
In the
following example, Mr. Corbyn uses an argumentative comparison with the
Second
World War to emphasize the plight of asylum seekers:
(5) Many soldiers who were
tortured during the second world war found
it
difficult to talk about their experiences for years. That is no
different from
the position of people who have been tortured in
CONSENSUS
(POLITICAL STRATEGY). To claim or insist on cross-party or national
consensus is a well-known political strategy in situations where the
country is
threatened, for instance by outside attack. Immigration is often seen
as such a
threat. Thus, Mrs. Gorman insists that the current immigration law is
the fruit
of consensus, and hence should not be tampered with:
(6) The Government, with
cross-party backing, decided to do something about the matter (Gorman,
C).
COUNTERFACTUALS
(MEANING, ARGUMENTATION). (See also Counterfactuals) “What would
happen, if…”, the typical expression of a counterfactual, is often used
in this
debate by the Labour opposition in order to suggest that the
conservatives try
to imagine what it would be like to be in the situation of asylum
seekers, an persuasive
argumentative move that is also is related to the move of asking for
empathy:
(7) I suggest that he start
to think more seriously about human rights issues. Suppose he had to
flee this
country because an oppressive regime had taken over. Where would he go?
Presumably he would not want help from anyone else, because he does not
believe
that help should be given to anyone else (Corbyn).
(8) If that happened in
another country under a regime of which we disapproved, the British
Government
would say that it was a terrible indictment on the human rights record
of that
regime that prisoners were forced to undertake a hunger strike to draw
attention to their situation (Corbyn).
(9) [Apparent Empathy] I
understand that many people want to come to
(10) [Apparent Denial] I did
not say that every eastern European's application for asylum in this
country
was bogus. However... (Gorman).
EUPHEMISM
(RHETORIC; MEANING). (See Taboo,
euphemism and political correctness).
The well-known rhetorical figure of euphemism, a semantic
move of
mitigation, plays an important role in talk about immigrants. Within
the
broader framework of the strategy of positive self-presentation, and
especially
its correlate, the avoidance of negative impression formation, negative
opinions about immigrants are often mitigated, especially in foreign
talk. The
same is true for the negative acts of the own group. Thus, racism or
discrimination will typically be mitigated as "resentment" or
"unequal treatment", respectively. Similarly Ms. Gorman in this
debate uses the word "discourage" ("to discourage the growing number
of people from abroad...") in order to refer to the harsh immigration
policies of the government, and thus mitigates the actions of the
conservative
government she supports. Similarly, the Labour (Corbyn) opposition
finds the
condemnation of oppressive regimes by the Government "very muted"
instead of using more critical terms. Obviously, such mitigation of the
use of
euphemisms may be explained both in ideological terms (ingroup
protection), as
well as in contextual terms, e.g., as part of politeness conditions or
other
interactional rules that are typical for parliamentary debates.
EVIDENTIALITY
(MEANING, ARGUMENTATION). (See also Evidentiality in grammar). Claims
or points of view in argument are more plausible when speakers present
some
evidence or proof for their knowledge or opinions. This may happen by
references to AUTHORITY figures or institutions (see above), or by
various
forms of Evidentiality: How or where did they get the information. Thus
people
may have read something in the paper, heard it from reliable
spokespersons, or
have seen something with their own eyes. Especially in debates on
immigration,
in which negative beliefs about immigrants may be heard as biased,
evidentials
are an important move to convey objectivity, reliability and hence
credibility.
In stories that are intended to provoke empathy, of course such
evidence must
be supplied by the victims themselves. When sources are actually being
quoted, evidentiality is linked to
INTERTEXTUALITY. Here are a two examples:
(12) The people who I met
told me, chapter and verse, of how they had been treated by the regime
in
EXAMPLE/ILLUSTRATION
(ARGUMENTATION). A powerful move in argumentation is to give
concrete examples, often in the form of a vignette or short story,
illustrating
or making more plausible a general point defended by the speaker.
Concrete
stories are usually better memorized than abstract arguments, and have
more
emotional impact, so they are argumentatively more persuasive. Of
course, the
right and the left each will have its own stories to tell:
(13) The Daily Mail today
reports the case of a woman from
(14) The people who I met
told me, chapter and verse, of how they had been treated by the regime
in
Iran--of how they had been summarily imprisoned, with no access to the
courts;
of how their families had been beaten up and abused while in prison;
and of how
the regime murdered one man's fiancée in front of him because he would
not talk
about the secret activities that he was supposed to be involved in
(Corbyn).
GENERALIZATION
(MEANING, ARGUMENTATION). Instead of providing concrete stories, speakers may
also make generalizations, in racist discourse typically used to
formulate
prejudices about generalized negative characteristics of immigrants.
Similarly,
in a populist strategy, conservative speakers may generalize the
negative
feelings against asylum seekers:
(15)
Such things go on and they get up the
noses of all constituents (Gorman).
HYPERBOLE
(RHETORIC). Hyperboles are semantic
rhetorical devices for the enhancement of meaning. Within the overall
strategy
of positive self-presentation and negative other-presentation, we may
thus
expect in parliamentary debates about immigrants that the alleged bad
actions
or properties of the Others are expressed
in
hyperbolic terms (our bad actions in mitigated terms), and vice versa.
Sometimes such forms of hyperbole are implied by the use of special
METAPHORS,
as we observe in Mrs. Gorman's use of "opening the floodgates" in
order to refer to the arrival of many asylum seekers. And conversely,
on the
left, Labour speakers will of course emphasize the bad nature of
authoritarian
regimes, and like Mr. Corbyn, will call them "deeply oppressive", and
the conditions of refugees coming from those countries "appalling".
IMPLICATION
(MEANING).
For many 'pragmatic' (contextual) reasons, speakers do not (need) to
say everything they know or believe. Indeed, large part of discourse
remains
implicit, and such implicit information may be inferred by recipients
from
shared knowledge or attitudes and thus constructed as part of their
mental
models of the event or action represented in the discourse. In debates
about immigration,
implicitness may especially be used as a means to convey meanings whose
explicit expression could be interpreted as biased or racist. Thus,
when Ms. Gorman
says that many refugees come from countries in
IRONY
(RHETORIC). (See Irony). Accusations
may come across as more effective
when they are not made point blank (which may violate face
constraints), but in
apparently lighter forms of irony. There is much irony in the mutual
critique
and attacks of Conservatives and Labour, of course, and these
characterize the
proper interactional dimension of the debate. However, when speaking
about
immigrants, irony may also serve to derogate asylum seekers, as is the
case for
the phrase "suddenly discover" in the following example, implying
that such a "sudden discovery" can only be bogus, since the asylum
seekers allegedly knew all along that they came to the country to stay:
(16) Too many asylum seekers
enter the country initially as family visitors, tourists, students and
business
people, and then suddenly discover that they want to remain as asylum
seekers
(Shaw).
LEXICALIZATION
(STYLE). At
the local level of analysis, debates on asylum seekers need to
express underlying concepts and beliefs in specific lexical items.
Similar
meanings may thus be variably expressed in different words, depending
on the
position, role, goals, point of view or opinion of the speaker, that
is, as a
function of context features. In conservative discourse opposing
liberal
immigration policies, this will typically result in more or less
blatantly
negative expressions denoting refugees and their actions, thus
implementing at
the level of lexicalization the overall ideological strategy of
negative
other-presentation. Thus, also in this debate, we may typically find
such as
expressions as "economic immigrants", "bogus asylum
seekers", or "benefit scroungers", as we also know them from the
tabloid press in the
METAPHOR
(MEANING,
RHETORIC). (See the other chapters on metaphor).
Few semantic-rhetorical figures are as persuasive as metaphors, also in
debates
on immigration. Abstract, complex, unfamiliar, new or emotional
meanings may
thus be made more familiar and more concrete. Virtually a standard
metaphor (if
not a topos) is the use of flood-metaphors to refer to refugees and
their
arrival, symbolizing the unstoppable threat of immigration, in which we
would
all "drown". Thus, Ms. Gorman warns for changes in the present law by
saying that such changes would "open the floodgates again". Another
notorious semantic realm of metaphors is to describe people in terms of
(aggressive, repulsive, etc.) animals, for instance asylum seekers as
“parasites”, as does Mrs. Gorman.
NATIONAL
SELF-GLORIFICATION (MEANING). Especially in parliamentary
speeches on
immigration, positive self-presentation may routinely be implemented by
various
forms of national self-glorification: Positive references to or praise
for the
own country, its principles, history and traditions. Racist ideologies
may thus
be combined with nationalist ideologies, as we have seen above. This
kind of
nationalist rhetoric is not the same in all countries. It is unabashed
in the
(17) Britain has always honoured the Geneva convention, and has given
sanctuary to
people with a well-founded fear of persecution in the country from
which they
are fleeing and whose first safe country landing is in the United
Kingdom
(Wardle).
NEGATIVE
OTHER-PRESENTATION (SEMANTIC MACRO-STRATEGY). As the previous examples
have shown, the categorization of people in ingroups and outgroups, and
even
the division between 'good' and 'bad' outgroups, is not value-free, but
imbued
with ideologically based applications of norms and values. Thus,
throughout
this debate, Mrs. Gorman describes asylum seekers in terms of “benefit
seekers”
or “bogus” immigrants. Negative other-presentation is usually
complimentary to
positive self-presentation.
NORM
EXPRESSION.
Anti-racist
discourse is of course strongly normative, and decries racism,
discrimination,
prejudice and anti-immigration policies in sometimes explicit
norm-statements
about what 'we' (in parliament, in the
(18) We should have a
different attitude towards asylum seekers (Corbyn).
NUMBER GAME
(RHETORIC, ARGUMENTATION). Much argument is oriented to enhancing credibility
by moves that emphasize objectivity. Numbers and statistics are the
primary
means in our culture to persuasively display objectivity, and they
routinely
characterize news reports in the press. Arrivals of immigrants are
usually
accompanied by numbers, also in parliament. The same is true for the
‘costs’ of
immigrants:
(19)
It would open the floodgates again, and
presumably the £200 million a year cost that was estimated when the
legislation
was introduced (Gorman, C).
POLARIZATION,
US-THEM CATEGORIZATION (MEANING). Few semantic strategies in
debates about Others are as prevalent as
the
expression of polarized cognitions, and the categorical division of
people in
ingroup (US) and outgroup (THEM). This suggests that especially also
talk and
text about immigrants or refugees is strongly monitored by underlying
social
representations (attitudes, ideologies) of groups, rather than by
models of
unique events and individual people (unless these are used as
illustrations to
argue a general point). Polarization may also apply to 'good' and 'bad'
sub-categories of outgroups, as is the case for friends and allies on
the one
hand, and enemies on the other. Note that polarization may be
rhetorically
enhanced when expressed as a clear contrast, that is, by attributing
properties
of US and THEM that are semantically each other's opposites. Examples
in our
debate abound, but we shall only give two typical examples:
(20) It is true that, in many
cases, they have made careful provision for themselves in their old
age, have a
small additional pension as well as their old-age pension and pay all
their
rent and their bills and ask for nothing from the state. They are proud
and
happy to do so. Such people should not be exploited by people who are
exploiting
the system (Gorman, C).
POSITIVE
SELF-PRESENTATION
(SEMANTIC MACROSTRATEGY). Whether or not in combination with the derogation
of outgroups, group-talk is often characterized by another overall
strategy,
namely that of ingroup favoritism or "positive self-presentation".
This may take a more individual form of face-keeping or impression
management,
as we know them from familiar disclaimers ("I am not a racist,
but..."), or a more collective form in which the speaker emphasizes the
positive characteristics of the own group, such as the own party, or
the own
country. In the context of debates on immigration, such positive
self-presentation will often manifest itself as an emphasis of own
tolerance,
hospitality, lack of bias, EMPATHY, support of human rights, or
compliance with
the law or international agreements. Positive self-presentation is
essentially
ideological, because they are based on the positive self-schema that
defines
the ideology of a group. Here is an example:
(21) I entirely support the
policy of the Government to help genuine asylum seekers, but...(Gorman,
C).
POPULISM
(POLITICAL STRATEGY). One of the dominant overall strategies of
conservative talk on immigration is that of populism. There are several
variants and component moves of that strategy. The basic strategy is to
claim
(for instance against the Labour opposition) that "the people" (or
"everybody") does not support further immigration, which is also a
well-known argumentation fallacy. More specifically in this debate, the
populism-strategy is combined with the topos of financial burden:
Ordinary
people (taxpayers) have to pay for refugees. Of the many instances of
this strategy,
we only cite the following:
(22) It is wrong that
ratepayers in the
PRESUPPOSITION
(MEANING). (See
Presuppositions –
Pragmatics). Discourses
are
like the proverbial icebergs: most of their meanings are not explicitly
expressed by presupposed to be known, and inferrable from general
sociocultural
knowledge. Strategically, presuppositions are often used to assume the
truth of
some proposition when such truth is not established at all:
(23) I wonder whether the
hon. Gentleman will tell the House what mandate he has from the British
people
to share their citizenship with foreigners?
(Gill).
VAGUENESS
(MEANING).
Virtually in all contexts speakers may use 'vague' expressions, that
is, expressions that do not have well-defined referents, or which refer
to
fuzzy sets. Vague quantifiers ('few', 'a lot'), adverbs ('very') nouns
('thing') and adjectives ('low', 'high'), among other expressions may
be
typical in such discourse. Given the normative constraints on biased
speech,
and the relevance of quantification in immigration debates, we may in
particular
expect various forms of Vagueness, as is the case for "Goodness knows
how
much", and "widespread" in the following examples:
(24) Goodness knows how much
it costs for the legal aid that those people invoke to keep challenging
the
decision that they are not bona fide asylum seekers (Gorman, C).
VICTIMIZATION
(MEANING).
Together with DRAMATIZATION and POLARIZATION, discourse on immigration
and ethnic relations is largely organized by the binary US-THEM pair of
ingroups and outgroups. Thus, in order to emphasize the ‘bad’ nature of
immigrants, people may tell horrible stories about poor nationals, such
as the
kids….
(25) Many of those people
live in old-style housing association
The categories and examples shown above are not limited to racist or antiracist social ideologies, or to socialist or conservative political ideologies. Virtually all categories also apply to macho and feminist or pacifist or militarist ideologies and their discourses. That is they are rather general resources groups and their members acquire and use in order to account for and defend their ideas and social practices. Indeed, we need not learn totally new ways of ideological talk and text as soon as we become member of or identify with another social or political group.
Conclusions
There is a close relationship between discourse, ideology and politics, in the sense that politics is usually discursive as well as ideological, and ideologies are largely reproduced by text and talk. Traditionally, ideologies are vaguely and negatively defined in terms of “false consciousness”. In a more contemporary, multidisciplinary approach, ideologies are described in terms of the axiomatic foundation of the social representations shared by groups. Such general ideologies form the basis of more specific group attitudes, which in turn may influence group members’ individual opinions, constructions or interpretations of specific events, as well as the social practices and discourses in which group members engage. In politics, ideologies specifically play a role to define political systems, organizations, movements, political practices and political cognition, all enacted or reproduced by political discourse. Underlying political ideologies are typically expressed in political discourse by emphasizing Our good things and Their bad things, and by de-emphasizing Our bad things and their good things. Such a general strategy may be implemented at all levels of discourse. Thus, in examples from a debate on asylum seekers in British parliament we see that there are many ways ideologies may be expressed, for instance in the actor descriptions, fallacies, disclaimers, metaphors, comparisons, euphemisms, hyperboles, and so on.
REFERENCES
Abercrombie, N., Hill, S., & Turner, B. S. (1980).
The dominant
ideology thesis.
Ball, T., & Dagger, R. (1999). Political ideologies
and the
democratic ideal.
Billig, M. (1982). Ideology and Social Psychology.
Billig, M. (1988). Ideological dilemmas: A social
psychology of
everyday thinking.
Billig, M. (1991). Ideology and opinions: Studies in
rhetorical
psychology.
Bourdieu, P., & Eagleton, T., (1994). Doxa and Common
Life: An
Interview. In
Chilton, P. A. (1995). Security metaphors. Cold war
discourse from
containment to common house.
Chilton, P. A. (2004) Analysing Political Discourse:
Theory and
Practice,
Chilton, P. A. , & Schäffner, C. (Eds.). (2002)
Politics as Text
and Talk: Analytic Approaches to Political Discourse, John Benjamins,
Duranti, A., & Goodwin, C., (Eds.). (1992).
Rethinking Context:
Language as an Interactive Phenomenon
Eagleton, T. (1991). Ideology. An introduction.
Eatwell, R. (Ed.). (1999). Contemporary political
ideologies.
Fairclough, N. (1989). Language and power.
Fairclough, N. (1995). Critical discourse analysis. The
critical
study of language.
Fowler, R. (1991). Language in the news: Discourse and
ideology in
the British press.
Fowler, R., Hodge, B., Kress, G., & Trew, T. (1979).
Language
and control.
Freeden, M. (1996). Ideologies and political theory. A
conceptual
approach.
Goodin, R. E., & Klingemann, H. D. (Eds.). (1996). A
New
handbook of political science.
Gramsci, A. (1971). Prison notebooks.
Gumperz, J. J. (1982). Language and social identity.
Hodge, B., & Kress, G. R. (1993). Language as
ideology.
Larraín, J. (1979). The concept of ideology.
Leach, R. (2002). Political ideology in
Pêcheux, M. (1982). Language, semantics, and ideology.
Potter, J. (1996). Representing reality: Discourse,
rhetoric and
social construction.
Seliger, M. (1976). Ideology and politics.
Van Dijk, T. A. (1998). Ideology: A multidisciplinary
approach.
Van Dijk, T. A. (1999).
Context models in discourse processing. In: van Oostendorp, Herre, & Goldman, Susan R. (Eds.), The construction of
mental representations during reading. (pp. 123-148).
Van Dijk, T. A. (2001). Discourse, ideology and Context.
Folia
Linguistica XXXV/1-2, 11-40.
Van Dijk, T. A. (2003). Text and context of parliamentary
debates.
In Paul Bayley (Ed.), Cross-Cultural
Perspectives on Parliamentary Discourse. (pp. 339-372).
Wilson, J. (1990). Politically speaking.
Wodak, R. (Ed.). (1989). Language, power, and ideology
studies in
political discourse.
Wodak, R., & Menz, F. (Eds.). (1990). Sprache in der
Politik -
Politik in der Sprache. Analysen zum öffentlichen Sprachgebrauch.
(Language in
politics - politics in language. Analyses of public language use).
Wodak, R., & Meyer, M. (Eds.). (2001). Methods of
critical
discourse analysis.
Zizek, S. (1994). Mapping ideology.
Keywords
Discourse, political discourse, ideology, categories of description, parliamentary debates.
Cross-references
Context, communicative
Context, sociocultural
Critical Discourse Analysis
Parliamentary Discourses
Biography
Teun A. van Dijk was professor of discourse studies at
the